Living with the results of extended life

Werewolf magazine, Issue 24, 28 June 2011.

http://werewolf.co.nz/2011/06/living-with-the-cost-of-prolonging-life/

Unfortunately, however, we cannot escape the fact that there is a limit to the amount society is able (or willing) to pay for health care. At some point one person’s treatment means that another will go without. Even if a needs-based approach to prioritising which patients and services receive funding is fairer than some other methods of allocation, considerable practical and ethical problems arise when we try to arbitrate between needs; ought we fund a drug that will save the life of a small number of people, or provide hundreds of hip-replacement operations that will improve the quality of life for a large number of patients?  Does a young patient be treated before an elderly one because the former will gain more years of healthy and productive life, or do we owe a duty to people who have spent their working lives contributing to society (and, via taxes, the health system)?  How much should be spent on palliative care compared to life-extending interventions?  A straight cost-benefit analysis measuring efficiency in terms of the quality and duration life gained for a particular intervention suggests that funding should be directed toward the young and healthy, but do we really want to live in a society where the elderly and terminally ill are discriminated against? On the other hand, we are facing a situation where the cost of healthcare is predicted to increase rapidly as the population ages.

Cause of death also has a marked influence on the overall costs of care.  Inpatient treatment accounted for 75% of the expenditure on patients in the final year of life, with the highest cost for cancer patients.  Another point of note is that while the average cost of treating a patient during the final year of life was just over $22,000, 17% of the total budget was spent on 66 patients (2.7%).  Without knowing the situation of each of these patients it is difficult to make any judgements, but it does raise the concern that aggressive treatment may have been provided to some people with a very poor prognosis.  This is of concern not only because such intervention is not an ‘efficient’ use of scarce funds, but also (and more importantly) because it may not be in the best interests of the patients.  Intervention when a patient has a poor prognosis may prolonged for a short time but at such a high cost in terms of quality of life that it is not worth it. Similarly, doctors need to be prepared to withdraw treatment if it is no longer effective, even if it means the patient will die.  We can now keep extremely premature babies alive, but many (if not most) will suffer serious physical and mental disability even if they survive, for example.  Similarly we can extend the life of cancer patients for weeks or months with chemotherapeutic, surgical or radiological treatment, but sometimes with severe side effects.  Although it is natural to want to fight for the survival of a baby or a young parent with every weapon in the medical arsenal, sometimes it is not the right thing to do.  Such decisions are very hard to doctors and families to come to, but rather than spend money on aggressive treatment in such cases, it would be better to divert it to palliative or hospice care.

Although hard decisions still need to be made about how much we spend on health care amount of money allocated to different health services are determined at political level. Even though the conversation is a difficult one, we need to continue discuss both the economics and ethics of health care at a national level, and perhaps we will find out that things are not as bad as we thought.

* There are a number of ways of allocating health care (or any other scarce resource). For example we could provide care to those that ‘deserve’ it (due to merit or societal contribution). Thus a long-serving philantropist might take precedence over a solo parent, or a civic leader over a gang leader for example.  Although on the face of it this has a certain appeal, the problem with a deserts-based approach is that it requires making moral judgements about people.  What we consider valuable can change over time, (the philanthropist may have made her money by asset-stripping former state companies, while the solo parent may be a wonderful parent and a great neighbour), and is the start of a slippery slope whereby some people’s lives are worth less than others.

Another approach would be to leave it to the free market (based on the ability to pay) or to individual effort (which is frequently measured in earning ability, but could also reflect whether one follows a healthy lifestyle). Although this could encourage people to take responsibility for ‘earning’ the right to healthcare (both financially and in terms of living healthy lifestyles), such distribution assumes that everybody begins on a level playing field and discounts both the impact of poverty on health and the disadvantage that arises from ill health itself.  Similar problems arise if we allocate everybody an equal share.  Overall, allocation on the basis of need seems to be the fairest method, despite its imperfections.

Comments

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *